Home :: Books :: Nonfiction  

Arts & Photography
Audio CDs
Audiocassettes
Biographies & Memoirs
Business & Investing
Children's Books
Christianity
Comics & Graphic Novels
Computers & Internet
Cooking, Food & Wine
Entertainment
Gay & Lesbian
Health, Mind & Body
History
Home & Garden
Horror
Literature & Fiction
Mystery & Thrillers
Nonfiction

Outdoors & Nature
Parenting & Families
Professional & Technical
Reference
Religion & Spirituality
Romance
Science
Science Fiction & Fantasy
Sports
Teens
Travel
Women's Fiction
Ethics without Ontology :

Ethics without Ontology :

List Price: $29.95
Your Price: $29.95
Product Info Reviews

<< 1 >>

Rating: 4 stars
Summary: Suggestive and Interesting, but Somewhat Underdeveloped
Review: There's a lot of interesting philosophy in this slim volume, but the arguments aren't filled out in the way they should be and too many of its discussions are left superficial and unnecessarily compressed. Nevertheless, this is definitely worth a look for people interested in meta-ethics (and in metaphysics). There's no doubt that Putnam is a major contemporary philosopher, and he seems to be in the process of developing a distinctive meta-ethical view. Part of that process is on display in the lectures constituting the first part of this book.

The focus of Part I, which encompasses the first two-thirds of the volume, is a sustained attack on the assumptions that Putnam believes underlie ontology (the study of what types of things exist) as it has descended from Quine's "On What There Is" and as it is practiced among contemporary analytic philosophers. There are two assumptions he hopes to undermine: (i) the assumption that there is a single right answer to ontological questions, and (ii) the assumption that that there is some close connection between ontological issues and issues of objectivity, since objective disciplines are those in which we can and do truly describe objects (i.e. facts, entities, properties, etc.). He thinks both of these assumptions are false, and that this allows us to draw certain conclusions about the nature and status of ethics. The most important conclusion is that we don't need some special ethical metaphysics--ethical entities, facts, or properties--to have ethical objectivity. So the argument here is largely negative, inasmuch as Putnam's fundamental aim is to clear away certain philosophical errors that have led people to be suspicious of the objectivity of ethics. (Naturally, this suggests that Putnam is committed to a positive project of arguing for some form objectivism about ethics--but the positive project is largely ignored here and the outlines of his objectivism remain unclear here.)

Putnam first argues against the assumption that there is a single right answer to ontological questions. Here he argues for what he calls 'conceptual relativity,' according to which the existence of the sorts of things with which ontologists are concerned is a matter of convention, of the way in which we choose to talk here. Consequently, there is no single right answer to the question of whether something (e.g. sets of objects) exists or not. There's no independent fact of the matter here; there's nothing to decide between the various answers. We have different ways of talking about these things, and Putnam thinks it's a "silly" question to ask whether one way of talking is to be preferred to another. It's not simply that we don't know enough to determine the right answer; it's not that the question is one we lack the resources to answer. It is, rather, that the question of which answer is "right" really hasn't been given a clear sense. But ontology as it is currently practiced rests on an assumption that these things aren't conventional, that there is a single right answer to these questions. Thus, if the thesis of conceptual relativity is true, there isn't any such answer and ontology is a hopeless enterprise.

According to Putnam, the other general problem with ontology is that it is connected to an assumption that there is an intimate connection between objectivity in various disciplines and the existence of objects (facts, entities, properties) as the subject of those disciplines. This is relevant to ethics because he thinks we should think of ethics as possessing "objectivity without objects." One of the traditional problems with understanding ethics as objective is understanding just what moral facts, properties, etc. are like. Putnam wants to argue that this apparent difficulty rests on a confusion about the nature of objectivity, for there don't have to be objective moral value entities or non-natural properties or moral facts in order for us to understand ethics as being objective. And he argues for this conclusion by drawing a comparison with logic and mathematics, disciplines that seem objective--they seem to admit of truth and falsity, to allow for allow for rational argument, etc.--and yet don't seem to be about distinctive sorts of objects. Putnam thinks a proper appreciation of the subject will reveal that the same is true of ethics.

Importantly, Putnam's advocation of a sort of pluralism underlies his thinking idea here. Language, he wants to claim, does many different things, and failing to recognize this can lead to the problematic assumptions contemporary analytic ontologists tend to make. Putnam himself draws the comparison of his ideas here with the Wittgensteinian idea that there several distinct language games, and that none of them is the ultimate to which all the others must be reduced. Moral language, logical language, mathematical language--these are all objective, and yet they don't describe facts in the way that scientific language and language about ordinary empirical objects do. They do something else, and it's only a failure to appreciate the manifold ways in which language is used--the many different uses to which it can be put--that leads us to think that all these uses of language involve trying to describe special sorts of facts. Thinking that we need to posit special ethical facts, properties, etc. to understand ethics as objective is to inappropriately apply standards from another discipline to ethics. What we need to realize about ethical objectivity, about ethical truth and rational ethical argument, is that an understanding of it is something we pick up only from within ethical discourse and practice.

As interesting as some of the ideas here are, this book could stand to be about twice as long as it actually is. The first part was originally a series of lectures, and it reads that way: it's unnecessarily repetitious in places, and too sketchy in others. Furthermore, it's not altogether clear what Putnam's positive view is supposed to be since he never explains just what ethical objectivity is supposed to consist in. And while Putnam's characteristic erudition is on display here--he draws on a thorough knowledge of, inter alia, contemporary analytic philosophy, logic, mathematics, and the history of philosophy--too often his invocation of other philosophers is used to paper over weaknesses in his own arguments.


<< 1 >>

© 2004, ReviewFocus or its affiliates